Sidestepping the semantics of “consciousness”

نویسنده

  • Michael V. Antony
چکیده

Block explains the conflation of phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness by appeal to the ambiguity of the term “consciousness.” However, the nature of ambiguity is not at all clear, and the thesis that “consciousness” is ambiguous between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness is far from obvious. Moreover, the conflation can be explained without supposing that the term is ambiguous. Block’s argument can thus be strengthened by avoiding controversial issues in the semantics of “consciousness.” There is a widespread tendency among researchers of consciousness to address the semantics of the term “consciousness” (and its cognates) when investigating the mental phenomenon, consciousness. Such terminological discussions, in my view, are typically poorly motivated, add little to the inquiry, and confuse matters more than anything else. Ned Block, in his important and influential target article (Block 1995t), also touches on the meaning of “consciousness.” He proposes that the term is ambiguous (sect. 4.2.2, para. 5), with senses corresponding to phenomenal consciousness (P) and access consciousness (A), among other senses less central to his aims. In contrast with many other researchers, Block motivates his semantic discussion of “consciousness.” His purpose is to expose a fallacy which he claims arises when researchers reason about consciousness (sect. 1). According to his diagnosis, the fallacy results from the conflation of P and A, and he explains the conflation by appeal to the ambiguity of “consciousness”: “An ambiguous word often corresponds to an ambiguous mental representation, one that functions in thought as a unitary entity and thereby misleads” (sect. 4.2.2, para. 8). While Block takes it upon himself to motivate his semantic discussion, I believe the reasons he provides are not quite satisfactory. For, as I shall argue, conflations between P and A can be explained without supposing that “consciousness” is ambiguous, indeed without entering into the semantics of “consciousness” at all. By avoiding controversial semantic claims regarding ambiguity, Block can strengthen his argument. If one explores the literature on ambiguity within lexical semantics, one discovers that things are in a bit of a shambles, but one also encounters serious attempts to theoretically accommodate a wide range of interesting phenomena related to ambiguity.1 For example, a distinction is often drawn between two kinds of ambiguity: homonymy and polysemy. Homonymous words are said to have unrelated senses (like a dog’s bark and a tree’s bark) and correspond to distinct entries in the lexicon; whereas polysemous words have more interrelated senses (like opening a window and opening with a joke) which are listed together within lexical entries. There also appear to be phenomena that involve subtle variations of meaning but no ambiguity. Cruse (1986), for instance, speaks of modulations of sense, where “a single sense can be modified in an unlimited number of ways by different contexts, each context emphasizing certain semantic traits, and obscuring or suppressing others” (p. 52). One of Cruse’s examples is “car” in “the car needs servicing” and “the car needs washing,” where different parts of the car get emphasized or highlighted (the engine and exterior, respectively) but there is no ambiguity (p. 53). A related example drawn from Pustejovsky (1996, p. 32) concerns the word “good”: it seems to express different properties in “a good car,” “a good meal,” and “a good knife,” but it would be rash to infer from this that “good” is ambiguous, since the list of such expressions containing “good” can be extended indefinitely. I think a reasonable case can be made for the claim that something like modulation occurs with “consciousness” – that there is a single, complex phenomenon, different features of which get highlighted by uses of “consciousness” across different linguistic contexts (sometimes phenomenal aspects, sometimes functional or cognitive aspects, etc.), but that the term “consciousness” itself is not ambiguous between P and A. In any event, it should be clear that anyone who wishes to convincingly argue that “consciousness” is ambiguous between P and A must enter into these rather messy semantic issues and exclude interpretations that treat “consciousness” as univocal. Block does not do that sufficiently, to my mind; nor do others who discuss the semantics of “consciousness.” Instead, it seems, new senses of “consciousness” are forever being offered, without constraint. But surely semantics is not that easy! (Notice, by the way, that so-called “stipulative definitions” do not in themselves issue in new meanings for natural language expressions. If a theorist stipulates that “consciousness” means milkshake, the English word “consciousness” does not thereby acquire BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2004) 27, 289–312 Printed in the United States of America © 2004 Cambridge University Press 0140-525X/04 $12.50 289 Continuing Commentary Commentary on Ned Block (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. BBS 18(2): 227–287. Abstract of the original article: Consciousness is a mongrel concept: there are a number of very different “consciousnesses.” Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech and action. These concepts are often partly or totally conflated, with bad results. This target article uses as an example a form of reasoning about a function of “consciousness” based on the phenomenon of blindsight. Some information about stimuli in the blind field is represented in the brains of blindsight patients, as shown by their correct “guesses.” They cannot harness this information in the service of action, however, and this isof the original article: Consciousness is a mongrel concept: there are a number of very different “consciousnesses.” Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech and action. These concepts are often partly or totally conflated, with bad results. This target article uses as an example a form of reasoning about a function of “consciousness” based on the phenomenon of blindsight. Some information about stimuli in the blind field is represented in the brains of blindsight patients, as shown by their correct “guesses.” They cannot harness this information in the service of action, however, and this is said to show that a function of phenomenal consciousness is somehow to enable information represented in the brain to guide action. But stimuli in the blind field are both access-unconscious and phenomenally unconscious. The fallacy is: an obvious function of the machinery of access-consciousness is illicitly transferred to phenomenal consciousness. a new sense, not even a new “technical” sense. At a minimum, a new public practice or use is required.) Block suggests that there are several equally legitimate ways to characterize ambiguity, and he favors doing so “in terms of conflation: if there can be conflation, we have ambiguity” (sect. 4.2.2, para. 7). However, if one takes semantics seriously as a scientific enterprise, then meaning presumably will have some nature and one will not be free to characterize ambiguity however one chooses. And even if there is some indeterminacy, some leeway for alternative characterizations, it is hard to avoid seeing Block’s construal of ambiguity in terms of conflation as ad hoc, given that it is conflation (of P and A) that he wishes to explain by appeal to ambiguity. Block, however, can avoid these tangled semantic issues, for conflation does not require ambiguity. He is of course right that ambiguous words often involve ambiguous mental representations (or, perhaps more accurately, distinct mental representations), and that such representations can give rise to conflation. However, all he really needs are the representations – distinct representations or distinct “elements” of complex representations – such that it becomes possible to unknowingly slide from one representation (or representational element) to another. While ambiguity suffices for that, it is unnecessary since mental representations or concepts are cut more finely than are word meanings. Consider commonsense and scientific concepts of water. Because they are different concepts, conflation is in principle possible; but “water” is univocal.2 Conflation is also possible where there is modulation (Cruse 1986). Consider how the sense of “full” is subtly modified across contexts in spite of being univocal: (1) a full bookshelf [no room across the shelf] (2) a full auditorium [all seats occupied] (3) a full balloon [stretched near capacity by a gas or liquid inside it] (4) a full swimming pool [nearly all its volume occupied by water] (5) a full swimming pool [contains a maximum number of people, as determined by safety regulations, comfort, etc.] Examples (4) and (5) furnish us with a means of demonstrating how modulation can result in conflation. Imagine a swimming pool that is scheduled to open on June 1, but by that date contains no water (and hence no people). And suppose an employee at the pool overhears the manager complaining on June 1 about the pool not being full. Finally, imagine the employee telling a friend how the manager is upset because the pool was not filled with swimmers on opening day, whereas all the manager really cared about is that it be filled with water (since the manager’s salary is independent of how many people are in the pool). In this example, both “kinds of fullness” are missing from the pool and, conflating the two, the employee fallaciously infers that the manager is upset because the pool was not filled with people. This closely parallels the fallacious reasoning about consciousness that concerns Block. However, the example shows that such reasoning, as well as the conflation on which it is based, can occur in the absence of ambiguity, since “full” is univocal. Perhaps something similar is happening with the word “consciousness” and the distinct elements of our complex mental representation of consciousness that represent phenomenal features and cognitive/functional ones. I believe Block would do best to explain the conflation between P and A in terms of something like “carelessly sliding over representational distinctions,” without committing himself to whether such distinctions are across distinct representations or elements within a single representation. And he ought not tie himself to the claim that the English word “consciousness” is ambiguous between P and A. Even if he believes it is, his argument does not depend on it being so. Block’s argument would thus be strengthened if such controversial semantic issues were avoided.3

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Spirituality and Theism in Organization: Characteristics of a Theistic Management

The decline of attention to the facade of modernity and the inclination toward spirituality and theism in the third millennium is the evidence of human natural tendency toward spirituality, theism, and faith. This is, also, to some extent connected to discussions of identity and semantics in organizations. This paper tries to review the works of researchers on spirituality and theism along with...

متن کامل

Application of Frame Semantics to Teaching Seeing and Hearing Vocabulary to Iranian EFL Learners

A term in one language rarely has an absolute synonymous meaning in the same language; besides, it rarely has an equivalent meaning in an L2. English synonyms of seeing and hearing are particularly grammatically and semantically different. Frame semantics is a good tool for discovering differences between synonymous words in L2 and differences between supposed L1 and L2 equivalents. Vocabulary ...

متن کامل

Declarative Semantics in Object-Oriented Software Development - A Taxonomy and Survey

One of the modern paradigms to develop an application is object oriented analysis and design. In this paradigm, there are several objects and each object plays some specific roles in applications. In an application, we must distinguish between procedural semantics and declarative semantics for their implementation in a specific programming language. For the procedural semantics, we can write a ...

متن کامل

The Comparative Semantics of ‘Recitation’ and ‘Chanting’ in the Holy Quran and Hadith’s Viewpoint

In linguistics, a study of the relation between word and meaning is called semantics. Semantics is a term for referring to study the meaning of elements of a language, particularly to study the real context of sentences and phrases of a language. The meaning of ‘recitation’ and ‘chanting’ in terms of Quranic, Hadith and idiomatic applications will be identified in this p...

متن کامل

Lexical Semantics and Selection of TAM in Bantu Languages: A Case of Semantic Classification of Kiswahili Verbs

The existing literature on Bantu verbal semantics demonstrated that inherent semantic content of verbs pairs directly with the selection of tense, aspect and modality formatives in Bantu languages like Chasu, Lucazi, Lusamia, and Shiyeyi. Thus, the gist of this paper is the articulation of semantic classification of verbs in Kiswahili based on the selection of TAM types. This is because the sem...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2004